Ethan
Siegel’s September 2, 2020, Forbes
article, “What Makes a Planet: Lessons Learned 14 Years after Pluto’s Demotion”
ironically indicates the writer has not learned any lessons from a decade and a
half of controversy and is simply doubling down on his insistence that Pluto
isn’t a planet, in spite of scientific discoveries over the last decade and a
half.
The
primary problem with Siegel’s article is its near-complete denial of the
continuing planet debate, blind repetition of the controversial IAU position,
and complete failure to acknowledge legitimate scientific opposition to that
position.
Siegel, an astrophysicist rather than a planetary scientist, misrepresents and
minimizes the community of planetary scientists who reject the IAU definition
in favor of a geophysical one with his statement, “Pluto doesn’t come close to
meeting the third criteria, and so only those who go by geophysical definitions
— where location and formation history are ignored — still consider Pluto a
planet in any way.”
That
last sentence is nothing less than denigration of the many planetary scientists
who prefer the geophysical definition with the false claim that they “ignore”
location and formation history.
Siegel’s assumed premise, that there are only three classes of planets—terrestrials,
ice giants, and gas giants, is false. This is the central weakness of his
article. He assumes there are only three types of planets because either he or
the IAU or both say so, without providing any supporting evidence for that
claim.
The reality is there are additional classes of planets, starting with the dwarf
planets. This term was initially coined by Alan Stern in 1991 to designate a
new class of planets in addition to terrestrials, gas giants, and ice giants.
When four percent of the IAU adopted their controversial planet definition
requiring an object to “clear its orbit” to be a planet, they misused Stern’s
term by stating dwarf planets are not planets at all but another type of object
entirely.
This claim is not borne out in New Horizons’ findings at Pluto or in Dawn’s
findings at Ceres. Both worlds are rounded by their own gravity and
geologically differentiated into core, mantle, and crust. Both have complex
planetary processes and probably belong in what should be yet another new
planet category, the ocean worlds—worlds with subsurface oceans that could
potentially harbor microbial life.
In
addition to his failure to disclose that orbit clearing was adopted by just
four percent of the IAU, most of whom were not planetary scientists but other
types of astronomers, Siegel also ignores the fact that the claim dwarf planets
are not planets at all was the decision of 333 individuals in a room on the
last day of a two week conference rather than some type of objective truth.
Beyond
repeating the claim that orbit clearing is a requirement for planethood, for no
reason other than the IAU dictated it, Siegel cherry picks classes of objects
he refers to as planets in spite of the fact that they do not meet the IAU
definition he so steadfastly supports. He seems to accept the idea that rogue
planets can be planets in spite of the fact that they do not orbit the Sun or
clear their orbits (they have no orbits to clear). He also seems to have no
problem referring to exoplanets as planets, in spite of the fact that they do
not meet the first IAU requirement, which is that a planet must orbit the Sun
as opposed to any star.
Most
of Siegel’s claims seem to be concocted by him, with no evidence to back them
up. For example, he refers to super-Earths as an “artificial class” without
justifying why he considers this class “artificial.” Analyses of exoplanet
discoveries made by the Kepler and TESS missions indicate super-Earth planets
with sizes between that of Earth and Neptune do, in fact, exist. We still know
little about them, including their percentages of rock versus gas, yet their
existence has never been disproven.
As
to the question of why our solar system does not have a super-Earth planet,
that is still a mystery. Scientists have observed a wide variety of exoplanet
systems, including some with multiple stars and some with several giant planets
all orbiting in different planes. They have discovered “puffy” planets, water
planets, hot Jupiters falling into their stars, and a wide variety of solar
system structures that suggest there very likely is more than one way for a
planetary system to form.
Significantly,
we have not yet found dwarf exoplanets, but that is likely because they are too
small to find with current technology. This will almost certainly change soon.
When exo-dwarf planets are found, will Siegel still hold to his claim that the
range of planet sizes is limited to “smaller than Mars and Mercury to larger
than the size of Jupiter?”
More
problematic is Siegel’s claim that Pluto somehow has a different formation
history than the larger solar system planets. This is pure conjecture.
According to a recent study cited by planetary scientist Phil Metzger, protoplanets
in early solar systems eventually grow large enough that their gravity stirs
the area around them, slowing their rotation rates until they accrete all the
material within their orbital zones. When they reach this stage, these
protoplanets become full planets or “oligarchs,” the largest objects in those
orbits. At this point, there are no other phases of planetary growth they fail
to reach.
Nearby
giant planets can keep other planets in their systems small by gobbling up
material from their orbits. Migration of giant planets in early stellar systems
can also do this. Both Mars and Pluto likely remained small because the nearby
giant planets accreted material from their orbits before they could. But other
than size, there is nothing inherently different between Mars and Pluto. Mars
has a smaller orbit to “clear” because it is closer to the Sun. The only reason
Pluto cannot clear its orbit is the fact that it is further from the Sun and
therefore has a larger orbit to clear.
Interestingly, calculations by planetary scientists confirm that if Earth were
in Pluto’s orbit, it would not clear that orbit either. This reveals a serious
flaw in the IAU definition—that the same object can be a planet in one location
and not a planet in another location.
Siegel and the IAU argue that Mars and Pluto are completely separate categories
of objects, yet both formed via the same processes. The only difference is the
amount of material that was near their orbits after they finished growing. This
is not a legitimate reason for putting these objects in two separate
categories.
Calculations by Metzger indicate that the hypothetical large planet in the
outer solar system, Planet X, would not clear its orbit even under the formula
cited by Jean Luc Margot and quoted in Siegel’s article, when it approaches its
closest position to the Sun, known as perihelion.
Furthermore,
Margot’s formula is flawed because planets can be in positions where they clear
their orbits only to be subsequently interact with other planets in their
systems and be ejected into much more distant orbits they cannot clear.
Contrary
to Siegel’s statement, the geophysical definition does not ignore an object’s
location. It simply does not make location a deciding factor for planethood. By
recognizing the non-dominance of the planetary subclass known as dwarf planets,
it acknowledges their location and dynamics while still classing them as
planets.
Meanwhile, Siegel and the IAU completely ignore dwarf planets’ intrinsic
properties, which are the same as those of the larger, rocky planets. Pluto is
70 percent rock, and Eris, being more massive, likely has a higher rock
content. In describing New Horizons’ findings at Pluto, Siegel ironically reads
off a list of planetary characteristics—an atmosphere with hazes, ice mountains
and plains that float on top of a liquid ocean, snowy weather patterns, and varied
surfaces that change over time, but then goes on to discount all of these in
terms of making Pluto a planet.
At
the same time, Siegel has no problem lumping dwarf planets together with
asteroids and comets, which are very different objects, the latter not large
enough to be rounded by their own gravity, solely due to their locations. He
says Pluto fits in much better with the Kuiper Belt Objects while ignoring the
fact that there are two very different types of KBOs—one type large enough to
be spherical and the other not. The latter are loosely held together piles of
ice and rock, as opposed to the complex dwarf planets.
Siegel says regarding Pluto, “In many ways, it’s more complex and has more
potential for interesting chemical reactions — possibly even including
biological activity — than bona fide planets such as Mercury.”
In
other words, Pluto has a multitude of planetary processes and features but isn’t
a planet because the IAU says so??? How does any of this make sense?
The fact is, the IAU’s so-called “third criterion,” that an object must clear
its orbit to be a planet, was concocted for the sole, non-scientific reason of
keeping the number of solar system planets small and excluding Pluto.
In summary, Siegel’s claims that our solar system has only eight planets and
that from the perspective of astronomers, Pluto was never a planet at all is
nothing more than an appeal to authority—which is exactly the opposite of the
scientific method!
Most astronomers do not study planets. Should planetary scientists tell those
who study black holes what a black hole is and is not? Asking astronomers who
study completely different fields to define planet makes no sense. It is akin
to asking podiatrists to define brain surgery.
After 14 years, here we are—at the same place we were in 2006 but with a lot
more knowledge of Pluto, thanks to New Horizons. The IAU and Siegel cherry pick
the data they want and use circular reasoning to make their points. None of that
makes dwarf planets, including Pluto, any less than a subclass of full planets.